The New Communication Regime of University‑Industry‑Government
Relations
Loet
Leydesdorff
Department
of Science and Technology Dynamics,
Nieuwe
Achtergracht 166, 1018 WV Amsterdam,
The Netherlands
e-mail:
<loet@leydesdorff.net>
Rearrangements in
institutional relations among universities, industrial research, and government
laboratories are a consequence of changes in the communication structures of
relevant scientific communities.
Recently, Gibbons et al. (1994) have proposed distinguishing
between disciplinary sciences with a traditional communication structure (Mode
1) and `network sciences' (e.g., biotechnology, artificial intelligence) at the
interfaces (Mode 2). These authors,
however, have not yet developed categories for analyzing scientific knowledge
production in Mode 2 from an evolutionary perspective, although they noted that
the concept of `reputation' at the interface should be specified differently
from reputation within a scientific community (cf. Whitley, 1984).
Scientific knowledge
production in Mode 2 requires a further integration of political, economic, and
scientific orientations in research practices.
At the level of a single system, however, integration implies
de-differentiation, and would therefore be unlikely to evolve. This potential paradox between
differentiation and integration can be understood by using concepts of
second-order cybernetics.
I shall argue that
systems of translations at the network level contain a translative or triadic episteme
in addition to functionally differentiated or `dialectic' systems of
communication. This trans-episteme
can be elaborated from an evolutionary perspective: the translations entrain
innovative dynamics between codifications.
The implications of this model for the further development of social
theory are specified with reference to the sciences, the economy, and the
political subsystem, respectively.
1.
Cultural Evolution and Historical
Reconstruction
Sociologists and economists have been fascinated
with the transition from the mediaeval high culture to the modern social
system. What happened to the social
system in evolutionary terms? How might
this transition be explained? Marx, for
example, discussed the advent of modernity in terms of changing class
relations; Weber emphasized the function of Protestant values in the emerging
social relations of modern capitalism.
In science studies, the latter thesis was elaborated by Merton (1937)
when discussing the social origins of the scientific revolution in 17th century
England, while, for example, Zilsel (1942/1976) analyzed the emergence of the
modern sciences in terms of the development of new scientific practices and
rearrangements in the division of labour (cf. Shapin and Shaffer 1985). Others have pointed to tensions internal to
the mediaeval system like the struggle over investiture (Luhmann, e.g., 1989:
262 ff.) or the revolution in communication brought about by the art of
printing (Eisenstein, 1979; Kaufer & Carley, 1993).
All
these different explanations assume that a transition at the system level
should be analyzed in terms of ex ante causes. From an evolutionary perspective, however, the emerging new order
is dependent on the specificity of the ex post selection. Selection optimizes in terms of functions,
independently of underlying structural arrangements. Thus, the variations leading to a transition are less important
for an understanding of the dynamics of a system than the selection mechanisms
which emerge (cf. Rosenberg, 1994).
While
the variation is initially only a perturbation, different sources of variation
can reinforce each other. For
stochastic reasons, the relevant distributions can become skewed, and then
exhibit structural properties (cf. Arthur, 1988). If repeated over time, the emerging structure may begin to
feedback on the `relevant' variation.
Thus, an emerging system self-organizes by selecting upon selections.
Selection
is recursive: some selections can be selected for (provisional) stabilization;
some stabilizations can be selected for globalization. A local stabilization can develop over time
into a identifiable trajectory; a global regime is expected to guide the further
developments of local trajectories by providing another layer of
selections.
In
summary: different structural dynamics can sometimes fulfill the same
functions, and different contexts may in other cases lead to a number of niches
as provisional stabilizations of a possible next-order structure. Functional differentiation can be defined
only with reference to this emerging next-order system. The focus on selection mechanisms, however,
generates an analytical problem: one observes the variation. The selecting instances have reflexively to
be specified as hypotheses, i.e. on the basis of theorizing about the emerging
systems.
1.1 The
Triple Helix
The
Triple Helix model takes the traditional forms of institutional differentiation
among universities, industries, and government as its starting point. The evolutionary perspective adds to this
historical configuration the notion that human carriers are able to reshape
these institutions reflexively (Tong, 1996).
The model thus takes account of the expanding role of the knowledge
sector in relation to the political and economic infrastructure of the larger
society.
From
an evolutionary perspective, the institutions can be considered as the
fingerprints of the communication patterns that have been functional for the
reproduction of the system hitherto.
The functionality of differentiation, however, leads its longer term
institutionalization. Thus, one can
distinguish between institutional differentiation and functional
differentiation in communications within and among these institutions.
Historically,
the systematic interaction between markets and sciences can be traced back to
the `scientific-technical revolution' in the second half of the 19th century
(Braverman, 1974; Noble, 1977).
Institutional differentiation between the nation state and the economy,
however, preceded this period. In other
words, the Triple Helix can be considered as a result of an interaction between
functional and institutional dynamics in society.
For
the analytical understanding of the Triple Helix model, one should first
cross-table these two relevant dimensions: the functional differentiation and
integration between sciences and markets, and the institutional difference
between private and public control.
Over time this cross-tabulation leads to a model of technological
developments in terms of university-industry-government relations.
What
is communicated in these relations?
Three dynamics have been distinguished in the relevant literature: the
economic exchange on the markets, the internal dynamics of knowledge production
and innovation-that
tends to upset the movement towards equilibrium-and
institutional governance of the interface at different levels (i.e., public and
private). Evolutionary economics has
analyzed this complex system from the perspective of the firm and in terms of
the latter's selections upon the co-evolution between technologies and
institutions (Nelson & Winter, 1982; Nelson, 1994). The distribution of reflexive agents,
however, adds a third helix to the specifically stabilized trajectories. A Triple Helix is by its nature unstable,
and thus this model enables us to study the various species of chaotic
behaviour that have been described in evolutionary economics (cf. Andersen
1994; Leydesdorff & Van den Besselaar 1994).
The
analysis of the infrastructure of knowledge in terms of ranges of possibilities
has become urgent in the light of proposals for reindustrialization at the
level of governmental and inter-governmental organizations (e.g., OECD,
1980). Since the late 1970s, national
coordination between industrial policies and science & technology policies
has taken hold in western countries that had earlier achieved the highest
degree of separation between institutional spheres (Porter, 1990; Nelson,
1993). Typically these policies involve
the development of closer connections between the state and industry, and
academia and industry. One implication
of the Triple Helix model is the analysis of the institutional binding forces
among different, yet interacting dynamics.
How do the institutional interactions recursively change the differences
in the communications that are also reproduced?
1.2 Layers
of Selectivity
Institutional
differentiation became possible when the order of modernity was fully
established during the 18th century.
Functional differentiation was constructed in Europe on the basis of a
century of (primarily religious) wars between 1550 and 1650. The episteme of the modern sciences
(Foucault, 1972), for example, can be distinguished from those of pre-modern
times in terms of the functional differentiation and the universalistic
orientation of communications. Note
that functional differentiation requires two levels of communication:
scientific communication, for example, has both a substantive value in itself
and a function for the emerging higher-order system of `universal'
theorizing. In principle, substantive
novelty (the `context of discovery') and methodological warrant (the `context
of justification') can then be distinguished analytically.
The
adjustment of underlying structures to functions under selection pressure can
be considered as a process of adaptation. Adaptation is a gradual process taking place through selection
from among possible formations, and therefore institutional codification can be
expected to lag behind processes of functional differentiation of
communication.
During
the 18th century-perhaps
with the exception of the United Kingdom-national
state formation had lagged: the organization of society remained in some places
entrenched in the mediaeval differentiation of nobility (France, Austria,
Spain, and Italy), while in other places regional differences opposed
centralization into a nation state (Germany, The Netherlands). At the end of this century, however, the
American and French revolutions established two nation states which were based
on the semantics of an institutional differentiation between civic society
(`the pursuit of happiness') and the national state (cf. Montesquieu, 1748). Although Napoleon tried to export the new
ideas about political codification as `universal,' development during the
period 1815-1870 (German unification) can be characterized with hindsight as
the social elaboration of this differentiation between civic society and the
various national states (e.g., Gouldner, 1976).
The
institutional development went side by side with the transition from mercantile
capitalism (universally oriented) into industrial capitalism (locally
organized). Marx noted this transition on
the occasion of the revolutions of 1848.
When he published Capital I in 1867, the new system was nearing
completion. After the American Civil
War (1865), the Japanese revolution of 1868, the Commune de Paris (1870), and
the subsequent German unification, the major nation systems were in place with
their respective capitalist economies.
Thus,
a dually differentiated system was established: the nation states contain
institutional mechanisms which in principle are able to reinforce specific
selections from the functional differentiations, for example by maintaining
national boundaries. While in the
functionally differentiated system, the control mechanism is firmly based in
the episteme-eventually
warranted by transcendental convictions-the
complex system may periodically shift control to institutionally warranted
structural elements (e.g., the bureaucracy).
Control then tends to become `trans-epistemic' (Knorr 1982). The system can also alternate between phases
of contraction and expansive modernization (cf. Freeman & Perez, 1988).
The
two dynamics can be combined in different ways. With hindsight, marxism can be considered as an ideology that
tends to take `the real existing human needs' as its system of reference, and
therefore emphasizes the institutional realization of power in
society. From a liberal perspective,
`power' and state organization are considered as codified embodiments of a
system of checks and balances with the aim of promoting the further (`free')
development of the subsystems defined in terms of functions (economy, science,
etc.).
When
the organization of society has become so complex that two mechanisms are
available for the integration, one should expect the possibility of a range of
possible interactions. At specific
sites the two selections may begin to reinforce each other, as in a
resonance. (At most places two
selections are expected to extinguish the signal.) Such `lock-ins' (Arthur, 1988) occur locally and discretely, and
if stabilized, the resulting patterns are expected to follow relatively
independent trajectories. In other
words, selections can be selected at some places for stabilization. In a next selection, a distribution of
provisional stabilizations can be selected for `globalization,' and then a
regime will be developed (Leydesdorff, 1994).
In
summary, the codification of two selection mechanisms at the level of society
makes it likely that a pattern of local interferences will emerge in a
co-evolution between these codifications.
The resulting patterns of communication can be considered as locally
distributed `lock-ins' or niches. This
distribution, however, contains the expectation of a next-order regime at the
global level. The theoretical question
remains whether one is able to specify this (co‑)evolution, and then to
articulate an expectation concerning the further development of the system.
2 TRANSLATIONS
2.1 The Institutionalization of Translations
The so-called `scientific-technical revolution'
took place at the institutionally organized interface between two functionally
codified systems, i.e. science and the economy. The new institutions (e.g. corporate laboratories) provided the
basis for an interaction between the codifications. Eventually, this development has led to the emergence of corporate
capitalism with its typical industrial R&D facilities and `technostructure'
(Galbraith, 1967).
Sustained
interaction is expected to change the codifications mutually. With reference to this `scientific-technical
revolution,' Braverman (1974: 167f.) noted indeed that `the key innovation is
not to be found in chemistry, electronics, automatic machinery, aeronautics,
atomic physics, or any of the products of these science-technologies, but
rather in the transformation of science itself into capital.' Conversely, the absorption of science by
capital has also transformed the latter: the productive forces are no longer
necessarily linked to the managerial decisions and instrumental action of
concrete people engaged in a labour process (Habermas, 1968). Economic selections can be discussed in
terms of representations (e.g., utility functions); scientific and technical
selections can no longer be considered as exogenous to this economic system
(Schumpeter 1939; Nelson & Winter 1982).
Thus,
the two functions can provide each other with resources and feedback on the
basis of their organization within an institutional framework. The institutional organization between the
two functional codifications allows for a helix of translations which
can be carried out at local interfaces (Latour, 1987). In a system of translations,
scientific communications are no longer selected only in terms of their
`truth'-value as their intrinsic codification, but also in terms of their
utility as another (no longer extrinsic) codification. Analogously, a production system can be
changed against (short-term) market pressures when innovations are selected
from a perspective of technological potentials.
2.2
Translation Systems
In translation systems, the selecting instances
may flip-flop between codes of meaning which co-evolve while selecting upon
each other. These systems are no longer
discursive systems that follow a single logic, but next-order translations that
recursively entrain the various logics which go into them as their
`genotypes.' The epistemological and
social consequences of such a transition are almost beyond imagination. While the previous episteme was based
on the geometrical metaphor of an internally consistent panopticum, the new one
is based on a multitude of perspectives.
Therefore, it requires algorithmic modelling and dynamic representations
(e.g., animations and video-clips). The
future possibilities of a system of translations extend beyond the
possibilities that can be imagined at any given moment, since phase transitions
and other forms of chaotic behaviour are expected in the dynamics of networks
(Kaufmann, 1993; Langford et al., forthcoming).
Systems
of translation are intuitively familiar from problems of interpretation when using
foreign languages. The same word may
have different meanings in different languages; various translations are
sometimes possible. A system of
translations can be understood as a system in which the interpreters
continuously communicate among themselves about the possible translations. Interpreters among natural language users
may try to settle their disputes by appealing to codifications like
dictionaries, but in a system of translations the dispute between different
perspectives is institutionalized.
If
the translators had completely different backgrounds in terms of languages,
their communication would vanish as in the case of the Tower of Babel. But since communication is noisy and
selective, the institutionalization of a translation system can lead to highly
specific second-order communications.
This emerging trans-episteme will in turn reinforce the mutual
understanding, and thus the self-understanding at lower levels of
interaction. Thus, the trans-episteme
enables the carrying agents to specify reflexively what may function as a
signal at a next-higher level, and what will be discarded as noise.
|
|
Figure 1 Differentiation (ij/ik)
and integration (i) of communication |
Figure 2 Differentiation
(ij) and translation (ijk) of communication |
Let me illustrate the
difference between communication and translation systems using two pictures. In Figure 1, three cycles are
depicted which have a common intersection.
The circles represent the different spheres of communication (with
respective codifications) that are possible in a pluriform society. In terms of communication processes, one
may think of the intersection as the common language (i), for example
the vernacular, in which all specialist jargons (ij and ik)
can be translated if sufficiently elaborated. As noted, the episteme of such a society assumes the
possibility of reintegration as its firm base.
In Figure 2 differentiation
has proceeded to such an extent that, first, the common zone of interpenetration
has disappeared. Second, the integrating
system is depicted as a hyper-cycle which can be generated by a series of
selections which the various communication systems employ in relation to
each other. However, the hyper-cyclic
communication is not expected to exist at any single moment. It is an emerging system, and indeed in
this case integration requires more complexity than differentiation. The system is integrated over time; at each
moment in time only a distribution of communications can be observed. The integrating instance can no longer be
observed since the selections can occur in different directions, and thus various
cycles may co-exist. Each system can
perceive itself as the integrating instance, since the criteria for integration
are different among systems, and the time horizons may be different as
well. Integration over time always
implies a translation at a receiving end as the system of reference.
In a communication
system under the previous episteme each human being is universalistically
assumed to be able to participate in the communication (on the basis of, for
example, sufficient training). But
this assumption has to be suspended when discussing translation
systems. The translation system is
based on a reflexive selection among communications on the basis of functionality
to the translation. The subdynamics
(e.g., languages) are reproduced as distributions at the supra-individual
level. The carriers of the original
communications are represented in systems of translation only in terms of the
quality of their communication among other communications. In other words, translation operates on
representations.
A
translation system can be considered as a network system that `lives' and
reproduces itself on an arrangement of underlying communication structures like
a parasite that is able to survive in a specific niche. If it survives, it will be able to establish
its own `population' dynamics. In
general, each next-order system tends to stand in orthogonal relation to the
previous levels, although it was originally constructed on the basis of
interactions among the constructing systems (Simon, 1973a). Therefore, the analytical categories have to
be respecified with reference to the emerging system.
3 CONSEQUENCES
3.1 Emergence
and Drifts of Trans-Epistemes
Translation
systems are not selective with respect to intentional actors but only with
their communications. Communication
systems may have to provide the carrying communicators with reasons, while
translation systems are able to select among the various communications for
functional reasons. Additionally, the
hyper-cycle enables translation systems to select communications from a
hindsight perspective. Thus, the
translation system contains an additional degree of freedom when compared with
a communication system: Translation systems are expected to handle more specificity
and complexity in the communication than communication systems. Accordingly, a higher-order trans-episteme
will develop: not the human intentions, but the unintended consequences of
interactions increasingly shape this system.
Although
it is presently perhaps only emergent, for example in cases of `high tech' or
`big science', the higher-order communication can be expected to assume control
upon its establishment, for evolutionary reasons. The emerging trans-episteme is expected to transform the epistemes
in the communication systems on which it rests. In addition to the communication of substantive novelty and
methodologically warranted codification (with reference to `truth'), high-tech
sciences are able to translate representations from other subsystems of society
into scientific knowledge, and vice versa, to legitimate research
results in `trans-epistemic' cycles of communication (Knorr, 1982). In other words, one is institutionally
warranted to change the code of the communication with hindsight if that is appropriate
for solving the puzzle under study.
Initially,
these changes of codes can be supported by divisions of labour in the relevant
`technostructures.' The crucial step,
however, is the establishment of competencies of communication among the
communicators that make it possible for the subjects involved to internalize
the anticipation of subsequent selections on each other's communications. Thus, the subjects are sorted in terms of
competencies for specific communications (Tobias et al., 1995; cf.
Habermas, 1981).
As
noted, the initial `lock-ins' occurred locally; therefore their pattern was
socially distributed. If these
processes can additionally be stabilized into co-evolutions, the
resulting patterns are expected to drive the system into higher-order
complexities of communication (Maturana, 1978; Nelson, 1994). The emerging trans-episteme is based
on interactions of the older differentiation between sciences and markets with
the institutionally organized differentiation between the political economy and
the post-Napoleonic state. From this
perspective, the history of science and technology in the twentieth century can
be considered in terms of an exploration of the potentials for recombining the
various subdynamics into a Triple Helix system.
Functional
differentiation and translative integration are mutually contingent upon each
other, but the operation is different.
As noted, functional differentiation requires the codification of the
communication, and, therefore, the distinction between substance and meaning of
the information (cf. Leydesdorff, 1995).
The high-tech sciences require hyper-cycles of communication in at least
three dimensions. `Triadic'
communication systems (ijk) are able to encompass the functionally
differentiated ones, and to translate them asymmetrically into each other (ij
6 ik). Thus, they are able to
change the code internally, and by evolutionarily alternating between codes
they seem to reconcile what was irreconcilable from the perspective of the
previous episteme. The solution
of problems (`puzzles') has heuristic value for the further development of the
discipline; truth (i.e., the value of the communication) has become a dynamic
function within the network of scientific communications. In other words, truth can be considered as a
discipline-specific meta-heuristic (Simon, 1973b). Thus, economic or political success is made to feedback on the
strength of one `truth' against another (cf. Latour, 1987).
The
emerging patterns are not expected to replace the older models, but to
incorporate them and to guide their future development. The next-order regime entrains the
trajectories on which it builds, and transforms them into subdynamics of the
more complex system (Kampmann et al., 1994).
3.2 Socio-economic Consequences
The transformation is expected to induce a
further differentiation in the socio-economic dimension as well. Indeed, scientific-technological innovations
generate product competition in addition to price competition. Product competition introduces dynamics into
the economic system over a time horizon which can no longer be reduced to
Pareto optimalization at each moment in time, as soon as the economic actors
(corporations, states) can strategically counter-act on the price mechanisms
(Schumpeter, 1939). Galbraith (1967:
178n.) noted that price maximalization and growth maximalization introduce
different selection criteria over time.
What
does this differentiation of the economic mechanism mean in substantive terms? Product life cycles are generated by
innovations which upset the movement towards equilibrium. Different phases of the life cycle lead to
different relations to customers, and thus to market segmentation. Market segments can be considered as niches
which can be functional for technological innovation (`incubators') or
dysfunctional in terms of constructing entrance barriers (`lock-ins'). Since all these processes occur at the same
time, complex evolutionary dynamics are generated within the economic system
(Leydesdorff & Van den Besselaar, 1994).
Highly
diversified and multinational corporations are sometimes able to take advantage
of these dynamics of scale and scope.
Thus, monopolistic tendencies have become endogenous to the economy
(Schumpeter, 1939). However, in a
knowledge-based regime the `movement towards equilibrium' can be structurally
upset: the economic perspective `genotypically' specifies one among different
subdynamics of the system. Other
subdynamics, like the replacement of input-factors by technological innovations
and the institutional mechanisms of normative appropriation and control can
steer the system just as intensively as the economic mechanism. There are no reasons for giving a priority
to one codification above another, except in terms of its functionality to the
emerging system. This functionality is
not a given, but is constructed in a series of translations among ranges of
expectations.
Thus,
technology studies itself has become an interdisciplinary field of
studies. Understanding product
competition requires in-depth study of the history of the major agents in a
field, of their social-economic contexts, and of the longer-term strategies and
policies of organizational actors and their network relations. Each study provides us with heuristics which
one should combine with systematic knowledge about relevant markets in order to
construct a complex evolutionary model.
The heuristics specify the selections that have proven viable in the
midst of a phase space of possible combinations.
3.3
Policy Implications
A major implication of the transition from
functional differentiation of communication to translation systems is that
political discourse has obtained a subsystemic character. Political interventions disturb the other
subsystems through operational coupling at the hyper-cyclic level, i.e. with
`unintended consequences.' As with the
other subsystems, this change in the status of government is based on an internal
differentiation of the political communication. The consequences of this transition, however, have not yet been
sufficiently reflected.
The
introduction of a further differentiation of policy making in terms of
functionality, (in addition to normative, i.e. hierarchical, control based on
codification,) is perhaps the most difficult one to accommodate because of
moral and constitutional blockages in political discourse. Political discourse already operates on
representations, but integration is achieved by human representatives. What does it mean for the political system
that integration is achieved in terms of discursive representations that
operate relatively independent from the carrying agents?
While
norms can be codified at the generalized level, functional policies are
specific, and they should take into account an evaluation of their systems of
reference in order to be effective. For
example, what may be functional in the case of `biotechnology' might not be
functional in the case of `advanced materials', and what may be functional for
the further development of University A might be dysfunctional for University
B.
Is
one justified in further differentiating in the discourse, and then making
trade-offs? In my opinion, the label
`liberal neo-corporatism' underestimates the kind of political strategies which
should be elaborated, by suggesting a reticent or orchestrating role for the
state. The translative intervention,
however, is specific at the network-level (Mode 2), but this specification has
to be legitimated with reference to its functions for the relevant systems (in
Mode 1). Without this elaboration of
the political discourse into different frames of reference and time horizons
(like in a cycle of strategic and operational planning) the knowledge-based system
may be weakened in its competition at the global level.
Thus,
policies should be based on assessments which are reflexively balanced against
normative premises within the policy system. When two selections can operate upon each other, the translation
may self-organize ways which enable the specification of institutional
arrangements in which public money and authority can be used to strengthen the
integration among subsystems. The word nexus
has been used for the result of such a constructive technology
assessment (Van den Belt & Rip, 1987).
As
noted above, selection selects for function, not for structure. If the function can be stabilized (for
example, in terms of a nexus), the feedback is expected to grow in
importance, and the underlying structures are expected to adapt (`survival of
the fittest'). Consequently, reflexive
`monitoring' is most functional for translative policies. The results of these `monitors' inform the
political decision process about options, but paradoxically their primary
function is the further development of the political discourse into an
internally differentiated system of translations that is able to sutain the
rather unintended outcome of an innovative nexus.
In
general, a translation has different functions for the various interacting
(sub-)systems. Translations are
asymmetrical: the systems interact, but thereupon each of the interacting
systems is reproduced in its own terms.
Reflexive translation systems are able to learn from their interactions
because the translated system is represented within the translating system so
that the latter can act on the former selectively. Thus, translation systems are able to strengthen their internal
dynamics in the complex environment of other translation systems.
The
price of such policies seems to be replacing the idea of normative control with
a reflexive focus on `unintended outcomes.'
The system of reference for the attribution, however, is different:
while in a functionally codified system politicians are held responsible for
their actions, a system of translations is no longer able to carry political
responsibility for crucial decisions.
For example, the European Commission can hardly be held responsible for
Europe's monetary unification. The
translation system is not accountable for its history since it is no longer
rooted in `real people,' but in communications among them. It selects from actions which can be
attributed to others.
4 The
Further Development of the Triple Helix
How
has society been differentiated and integrated in modern and post-modern
capitalism, and how can one envisage room for new recombinations of these
different dynamics? I have argued that
three major distinctions are required for a parsimonious description, namely:
(i) the functional differentiation and corresponding codification in the
communication constructed mainly in the 17th and 18th centuries, (ii)
institutional differentiation between the economy and the nation states
(constructed mainly in the first half of the 19th century); and (iii) the
distributed integration of patterns of functional and institutional
differentiation since the scientific-technical revolution of the period
1870-1890.
The
emerging trans-episteme of the triple helix transforms the sciences into
disciplinarily specific heuristics which contain their older (disciplinary)
functions as meta-heuristics.
Algorithmic puzzle solving and invention based on analytical
recombinations among different domains have become cornerstones of
scientific-technological developments.
Analogously, the transition tends to transform the economy into a
complex mixture of price and product competition that exhibit non-linear
dynamics. Policy making is challenged
to distinguish internally between a state apparatus which is functional for the
development of the triple helix, and normative control. Strategic and operational considerations can
be related, for example in planning cycles.
These
transitions towards an `information society' in which each subsystem contains sufficient
complexity to internally translate representations of itself, are currently
tendencies, and far from completed.
From an evolutionary perspective, a more complex system however is
expected to entrain its previous carriers as its instantiations, but
reflexively. Various forms are
explored, and some are eventually selected.
The translation systems can develop at high speeds since the Triple
Helix is no longer `rooted' in human beings, but in interactive and reflexive
discourses. The recursivity of the
selections can be computer supported so that the results can be valuable even
if counter-intuitive to the `natural' systems carrying to the system (cf.
Leydesdorff, 1994).
An
`artificial evolution' is expected to transform the economy at an increasing
pace, since it can deal with more complexity than its predecessors (Andersen,
1994). As noted, the emergence of `big
science' during the 20th century can be considered as the historical
acculturation of the new trans-episteme of science-technology-economy. The reflexive organization of its
institutional patterns in new forms of S&T policies was apparently delayed
until the oil crises of 1970s, when the post-war system entered into a series
of crises at the level of the global economy.
The gradual emergence of stable patterns of scientific reproduction in
fields like `artificial intelligence', `biotechnology', and `advanced
materials' in the 1980s indicates the viability of the triadic model of
communication (Van den Besselaar & Leydesdorff, 1993 and 1996; Ahrweiler,
1995; Leydesdorff & Gauthier, 1996).
In my opinion, the global system is heavily experimenting with various
formats for the institutionalization of knowledge based translations.
REFERENCES
Ahrweiler,
Petra (1995). Künstliche Intelligenz-Forschung in Deutschland. Die
Etablierung eines Hochtechnologie-Fachs [Artificial Intelligence Research in
Germany: The establishment of a high-tech field]. Münster/New York, Waxmann.
Andersen,
Esben S. (1994). Evolutionary Economics: Post-Schumpeterian Contributions. London,
Pinter.
Arthur,
W. Brian (1988). `Competing technologies.' In Dosi et al., pp. 590‑607.
Blauwhof,
Gertrud (1994). `Non-equilibria Dyanmics and the Sociology of Technology,' in
Leydesdorff & Van den Besselaar, pp. 152-66.
Braverman,
Harry (1974). Labor and Monopoly Capital. New York/London, Monthly
Review Press.
Dosi,
Giovanni, Chistopher Freeman, Richard Nelson, Gerald Silverberg, and Luc Soete
(Eds.) (1988). Technical Change and Economic Theory. London: Pinter.
Eisenstein,
Elizabeth L. (1979). The printing
press as an agent of change, communications, and cultural transformation in
early modern Europe, Vols. 1-2. London: Cambridge University Press.
Elzinga,
Aant (1985). `Research, Bureaucracy and the Drift of Epistemic Criteria,' in:
Björn Wittrock and Aant Elzinga (Eds.), The University Research System. Stockholm, Almqvist & Wiskell, pp.
191-217.
Foucault,
Michel (1972 [1969]). The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York, Pantheon.
Freeman,
Chris and Perez, Carlota (1988). `Structural crises of adjustment, business
cycles and investment behaviour', pp. 38-66 in Dosi (1988).
Galbraith,
John K. (1967). The New Industrial State. Penguin.
Gibbons,
Michael, Camille Limoges, Helga Nowotny, Simon Schwartzman, Peter Scott, and
Martin Trow (1994). The new production of knowledge: the dynamics of science
and research in contemporary societies. London, Sage.
Gouldner,
Alvin W. (1976). The dialectic of ideology and technology. London,
Macmillan.
Habermas,
Jürgen (1968). `Technik und Wissenschaft als "Ideologie",' pp. 48-103
in Technik und Wissenschaft als "Ideologie". Frankfurt a.M.,
Suhrkamp.
Habermas,
Jürgen (1981). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Frankfurt a.M.,
Suhrkamp.
Kampmann,
Christian, Christian Haxholdt, Erik Mosekilde, and John D. Sterman (1994).
`Entrainment in a Disaggregated Long-Wave Model.' Pp. 109-24 in Leydesdorff and
Van den Besselaar (1994).
Kaufer,
David S., and Kathleen M. Carley (1993). Communication at a Distance: The
Influence of Print on Sociocultural Organization and Change. Hillsdale NJ,
Erlbaum).
Kaufmann,
Stuart A. (1993). Origins of Order. New York, Oxford University Press.
Knorr-Cetina,
Karin D. (1982). "Scientific
communities or transepistemic arenas of research? A critique of quasi-economic models of science," Social
Studies of Science 12, 101-30.
Langford,
Cooper H., R. Douglas Burch, & Martha W. Langford (1997). `Some Canadian
Experience of Innovation Crystallization from Networks Involving Industry and
Universities under Government Influence,' Science & Public Policy
(forthcoming).
Latour,
Bruno (1987). Science in Action. Milton Keynes, Open University.
Leydesdorff,
Loet (1994). `The Evolution of Communication Systems', Int. J. Systems
Research and Information Science 6, 219-30.
Leydesdorff,
Loet (1995). The Challenge of Scientometrics: the development, measurement,
and self-organization of scientific communications. Leiden: DSWO Press,
Leiden University.
Leydesdorff,
Loet & Van den Besselaar, Peter, (Eds.) (1994). Evolutionary Economics
and Chaos Theory: New Directions in Technology Studies. London, Pinter.
Leydesdorff,
Loet & Élaine Gauthier (1996). `The Evaluation of National Performance in
Selected Priority Areas using Scientometric Methods,' Research Policy
(forthcoming).
Leydesdorff,
Loet & Van den Besselaar, Peter (1997). `Technological development and
Factor Substition in a Complex Dynamic System', Journal of Social and
Evolutionary Systems (forthcoming).
Luhmann,
Niklas (1989). Gesellschaftsstruktur und Semantik III (Frankfurt a.M.:
Suhrkamp).
Maturana,
Humberto R. (1978). `Biology of language: the epistemology of reality.' Pp.
27-63 in Miller, G. A. and Lenneberg, E. (Eds.), Psychology and Biology of
Language and Thought. Essays in Honor of Eric Lenneberg. New York, Academic
Press.
Marx,
Karl (1867). Das Kapital I. Hamburg, Meisner.
Merton,
Robert K. (1938). Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century
England. Bruges, Saint Catherine Press.
Montesquieu,
Charles de Sécondat (1748). De l'esprit des lois. Paris.
Nelson,
Richard R. (Ed.), (1993). National Innovation Systems: A comparative study.
New York, Oxford University Press.
Nelson,
Richard R. (1994). `Economic Growth via the Coevolution of Technology and
Institutions', pp. 21-32 in Leydesdorff & Van den Besselaar (1994).
Nelson,
Richard R. and Sidney G. Winter (1982). An Evolutionary Theory of Economic
Change. Cambridge, Mass., Belknap Press.
Noble,
David (1977). America by Design. New York, Knopf.
OECD
(1980). Technical Change and
Economic Policy. Paris, OECD.
Porter,
Michael E. (1990). The Competitive Advantage of Nations. London,
Macmillan.
Rosenberg,
Alexander (1994). Instrumental Biology, or, the Disunity of Science.
Chicago, Chicago University Press.
Schumpeter,
Joseph A. (1939). Business Cycles: A Theoretical, Historical and Statistical
Analysis of Capitalist Process. New York, McGraw-Hill.
Shapin,
Simon and Simon Shaffer (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle
and the experimental life. Princeton NJ, Princeton University Press.
Simon,
Herbert A. (1973a). `The Organization of Complex Systems,' pp. 1-27 in Pattee,
H. H. (Ed.), Hierarchy Theory: The Challenge of Complex Systems. New
York, George Braziller Inc.
Simon,
Herbert A. (1973b). `Does scientific discovery have a logic?' Philosophy of
Science 40, 471-80.
Tobias,
Sheila, Daryl E. Chubin, & Kevin Aylesworth (1995). Rethinking Science
as a Career: Perceptions and Realities in the Physical Sciences. Tucson,
AZ, Research Corporation.
Tong,
Jian (1996). `Reflections on Human Capital Theory and Niche Theory in
Evolutionary Economics,' Paper at the Triple Helix Conference, Amsterdam
1996.
Van
den Belt, Henk & Rip, Arie (1987). `The Nelson-Winter-Dosi model and
synthetic dye industry," pp. 135-58 in: Bijker, W. et al. (Eds.), The
Social Construction of Technological Systems. Cambridge, Mass., MIT.
Van
den Besselaar, Peter & Loet Leydesdorff (1993). `Research Performance in
Artificial Intelligence and Robotics. An international comparison'. AI
Communications 6, 83-91.
Van
den Besselaar, Peter & Loet Leydesdorff (1996). `Mapping Change in
Scientific Specialties: A Scientometric Reconstruction of the Development of
Artificial Intelligence', Journal of the American Society for Information
Science 47, 415-36.
Whitley,
Richard D. (1984). The Intellectual and Social Organization of the Sciences.
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Zilsel,
Edgar (1976). Ursprünge der neuzeitlichen Wissenschaft. Wolfgang Krohn,
Hrsg. (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp).